Very few, if any,
societies have ever arrived at a workable and sustainable consensus about how to
distribute desirable scarce goods. The problem is exacerbated when the goods
identified as desirable, notably money and fame, are inherently scarce because
relative. If you extend the range to include, for example, happiness or virtue or
wisdom - well, then things might get a bit easier. If you can identify goods
where your gain is not necessarily my loss, so much the better. But for many people
that’s a bit too subtle; their understanding is limited to zero-sum games:
there’s a cake and any bit you get is a bit I don’t get.
A recent British Prime
Minister, David Cameron, praised those who took the sharp-elbowed approach. If
you want something scarce, then force yourself to the front of the queue. If
you knock over an old lady on the way there, well, that’s life which is about
grabbing what you can. President Trump agrees; he has grabbed many things on
his way to the top and he will do whatever it takes to stay there - say, dirt
on Joe Biden’s son as quid pro quo for US military aid.
I grew up at a time
when it was thought that the distributional problem could be solved in a
consensual way if societies operated meritocratically: you should get more of
the desirable goods only if you in some way merited them. Talent, hard work, a
track record of success were among the measures of merit. Race, Class, Sex were
irrelevant. Though it was rarely articulated bluntly meritocracy was also a
blatant alternative to inheritance; if you were really going to be
meritocratic, then the House of Lords had to go and inheritance of serious wealth
had to go too.
All general theories
have their problems. At Oxford in the 1960s, one of my leftist friends reckoned
it a problem deserving of serious consideration (his father in the wine trade),
How should the finest wines be distributed after the revolution? Clearly,
ability to pay would no longer be acceptable (or possible). Would merit work?
Could you demonstrate through attendance at wine tasting classes that you had a palate deserving of a Premier Cru? And so on through many rounds of drink….
Nowadays, no one is very
keen on meritocracy. The favoured alternative is representation though no one has yet produced a definitive tome listing
all the relevant parameters for who should be represented and where. I have
tried to do the math, and once you move into multi-dimensional (intersectional)
representation it is very hard to
formulate what would count as a situation in which it would be true that For all values of the variables X and Y, X is fairly represented in Y.
But basically the where is fame and money and the who is specified in terms of a few
identities: ethnicity (but how many ethnicities
are there?) and sex and/or gender (with
a lot of ongoing debate there: is the Board of Directors gender balanced if
half are males by birth and men by identity and the other half women by
identity but with male appendages still in place? Trans ideologists seem
obliged to say that the answer to that is Yes).
Nobody seems much
worried about class anymore because
the working class, rather awkwardly, has its own identity politics: in the USA
it’s Trump and in England it’s Brexit. The identity politics with which Douglas
Murray is concerned is a middle class thing; it’s about access to money and
fame.
For example, when
(apparently Caucasian) Sierra Boggess was cast to play Maria in a production of
West Side Story one objection on
Twitter read “You are a Caucasian woman and this character is Puerto Rican. It’s
not like you’re hurting for job opportunities. Stop taking roles from actors of
colour” (Murray, pages 142-43).
Well, to me that’s
just an inversion on a standard working class complaint against immigrants They come here and take our jobs. In this
case, Puerto Ricans having come to mainland USA (as US citizens, they have always
had free movement rights) now claim back jobs which have been stolen from them.
This zero-sum idea of theft is
central to identity politics, most notably in the doctrine of cultural
appropriation. Nobody supposes either that immigrants make jobs happen or that culture grows by appropriation. Human beings just seem to find positive-sum
thinking too hard.
But there is more to
contemporary identity politics than non-meritocratic competition for scarce
goods. There is a strong sectarian or theological element with which Murray is
largely concerned and against which he argues and where I find very little to
disagree with. The hate-filled bullying behaviour of some young people who
think they have virtue on their side repeatedly reminds me both of the American
witch hunt tradition and of Jew-baiting on the streets of Hitler’s Germany. It
is not the politics of the democratic Left; it has more in common with the
politics of the worst Right - including an extraordinary degree of racism which
Murray documents.
Leave aside the bullying, it is also the case
that identity theologians secure their prominence - their five minutes of fame
on Twitter - by finding ever-new impossible things for us to believe before breakfast. Murray singles out what trans
ideologists expect us to believe and makes a restrained case against, urging caution
but also flagging up the ridiculous. Eventually I guess the impossible trans beliefs
will go the way of the Holy Trinity; whether they know it or not, most of those
who are still Christians are Unitarians not Trinitarians despite the residual efforts
of England’s state church.
Meanwhile, the impossible beliefs are doing a great
deal of harm, notably in university humanities and social science departments which have
cheerfully converted themselves into seminaries where nothing is studied or
argued, and everything simply asserted and endlessly repeated even if (as with Judith Butler’s prose) it is often confused or simply unintelligible.
I thought Murray’s
book very well argued and surprisingly nuanced for a writer whose metatags
(Eton, Oxford, Henry Jackson society, neocon, Leaver, ….. the Spectator) are so unpromising. The
book is perhaps at its most effective when he looks to Martin Luther King for a
defence of what later came to be called Big Tent politics. The general idea should be
to find things we have in common, not ways of endlessly asserting the desire
not to be common.
*
Recently, I tried to
write a memoir of my years as an Oxford undergraduate, both personal and
political. As concerns the political, I arrived in 1965 as an eighteen year old
member of the Labour Party who had very recently knocked on his neighbours’
front doors to secure the election of a Labour government; three years’ later I
graduated as a supporter or even member (I think I had a card) of the
Revolutionary Socialist Students Federation (which may or may not have had an apostrophe
…). To put it anachronistically, during my three years at Oxford, I Woke.
But then trying to
remember things I realised something which may now seem odd. However Woke I may
have been - and this is not just true of me - that didn’t mean that you did not
talk to the Unwoke (who were legion), did not debate with them, did not listen
to them. And they reciprocated. It occurred to me, for example, that every week
when he lectured, arch-liberal and critic of Marxism Isaiah Berlin pulled in a
very full house and a significant part of that house was the Oxford Left which
turned out in force, not to heckle or barrack, but to listen to the most
mesmerising lecturer Oxford had on offer. I would not be pushing it if I said
that when you took your place you looked around to make sure that your fellow
lefterrati were there with you, rather as if you were at the theatre (which, of
course, you were). If anyone had suggested that Isaiah Berlin should be No
Platformed it would have produced bemusement or merriment. We had enough
confidence in our own convictions not to need to suppress other people’s (and
that may be one clue to understand where we have got to now).
It occurred to me that
age might have made me rose tinted in thus presenting the Left as indulgently liberal
so I looked for some external confirmation and found it indirectly in - doyen of the Oxford Left - Tariq
Ali’s Street Fighting Years,
originally published in 1987 and re-issued in a 2018 version which I am using.
He writes about his time in Oxford where by 1966 he was already well-known as
an activist and trouble-maker. That does not stop the local Conservative MP,
Monty Woodhouse from embarrassing me on
more than one occasion He used to stop me in the street and say “I am to
the left of the local Labour candidate [Evan
Luard - TP] on immigration, on Vietnam, on Rhodesia and probably also on
economic measures. But you and your friends will be voting, I take it, for him”
To which I replied that we were voting
for parties not individuals and moved off rapidly … (page 138)
So it was quite
possible for a Tory toff (later the 5th Baron Terringon) and a
revolutionary toff to josh in a civil way with each other on the streets of
Oxford - and for Tariq Ali to tell the story twenty years’ later in a way which
does credit to his opponent.
It’s true that very
shortly after, end 1968-early 1969, quite a few of us did place one limit on our
tolerance - just one, and after quite a lot of debate which in my case made me
very familiar with John Stuart Mill’s On
Liberty. Mill argues that free speech loses its privilege when the circumstances of an utterance constitute
it into an incitement to violence of some kind. He gives an example: you should
generally be free to say that corn dealers are starvers of the poor, but not to
address those words to an already excited mob standing in front of the local
corn dealer’s house. On this basis, I concluded - and argued in meetings - that
it was legitimate to try to stop Enoch Powell’s countrywide stump of political speeches since they
constituted an incitement to violence, unintentional perhaps but their effect
clear enough on streets which were becoming unsafe for black people. I had no
problems with the idea of Powell addressing, say, a university seminar -
indeed, I had attended one that he gave in Oxford and I simply sat a few feet away
from him and listened. I agreed with Mill: circumstance makes a difference.
The blind spot in my
thinking was the rather too easy assumption that we could take the law into our
own hands. On the statute books, incitement was an offence so why not appeal to
the state (as people do now)? After all, the state had more resources at its
disposal than we did. Equally, the exception made for Powell was arrived at with some hesitation and doubt; it was a last line of resort not the first choice as it now seems to be (Murray provides examples).
No comments:
Post a Comment